For the best formatting of this chapter's text, please download the free PDF file and/or purchase the paperback.
Overview
What, if any, kinds of actions done to try to improve the
treatment of animals (including, perhaps, trying to eliminate various uses of
animals) are morally permissible? Which, if any, are morally obligatory?
Changing our diets? Educating others? Working for larger cages and more humane
treatment, or for the abolishment of (some) animal use industries, or both? Trying to change the laws to
better protect animals? Illegal actions (done covertly or openly)? Undercover
investigations to reveal animal abuse? Rescuing or releasing animals from
animal use industries? Exposing people and businesses who support harmful
animal use? Violence of any kind, ever? Threats of violence? Terrorism? We will explore a range of
tactics and attempt to evaluate them morally.
Criticisms or Complaints about (Some) Activists Have No
Implications for the Morality of Animal Use
“Welfarism” & “Welfarists” versus “Animal Rights” &
“Abolitionists”: Ends and Means
A current heated controversy among animal advocates is
whether they should be – as some describe it – either advocates of “animal welfare” and “welfare reforms,” or advocates for “animal rights” and the
“abolition” of harmful animal use, or both.
These terms are often ill-defined and not carefully thought through. This can
lead to needless conflict among animal advocates and an inability to understand
what kind of information might help resolve these debates. Thinking about
“ends” or “goals” and “means” or “strategies” can help us understand these
distinctions and better assess (and perhaps overcome)
this debate amongst activists.
First, ends: what would be a
morally acceptable end goal for the
treatment of animals? What kind of world would we have if all animals were
treated in morally permissible ways, where we could say, “We have achieved the
moral goal for how animals ought to be treated, since none are treated wrongly
anymore?”
Regan’s cat case presents two broad
options – among many – for such a goal:
Anyone who claims (C) is an acceptable goal or end we can
call a “welfarist”: they believe that once certain
kinds of harms to animals are minimized or eliminated, it is still usually
morally permissible to seriously harm animals, e.g., by killing them.
Their view might vary depending on
the purposes behind these harms, of course. And there are important details,
e.g., about which harms are permissible to cause and which aren’t, that they
would need to explain so we fully understand the view. And, most importantly,
whether any arguments in favor of welfarism are sound and withstand objections
is something we would want to think about very carefully.[1]
Anyone who
believes that (C) is deficient for an ideal goal and that (D) is that ideal we
might call a “genuine” animal rights advocate. Or, so that we say what we
really mean, we could just say they believe that seriously harming animals is typically morally wrong, even if they are
housed in comfortable cages, treated gently and killed painlessly. We would
want to understand their reasons for why they think that, and whether any
arguments in favor of this kind of view are sound and withstand critical
scrutiny is something we would also want to think about very carefully.
Beyond the
question of acceptable or ideal final goals or ends for animals is the question
of “means”: what sort of actions, policies, strategies, campaigns, and other
activist activities will be the most effective means toward the desired end goal for animals? In particular, if
the goal is (D), the “animal rights” end, what should be done now to best achieve this, or get us
closest to it, as soon as possible?
Here is
where the debate begins. Should we now campaign for larger cages, and, once
successful with that, then campaign for “no cages” – i.e., argue that animals
shouldn’t be used in the first place? (Or should some activists do the former
and other activists the latter?) The former might
lead to some small improvements now (or it might not), but it also might
forestall or prevent greater improvements that might have occurred had the focus been on “empty cages.” On the
other hand, campaigns for “empty cages” might
fall on too many deaf ears and yield no short term improvements. But perhaps
enough ears eventually will hear the message and this will result in widespread
abolition of animal use, perhaps
incrementally, one industry or sub-industry after another. Or maybe not.
These
debates are often divisive, but it’s not clear that they should be. For one,
they often involve matters that are largely speculative, such as the long-term
effects of some campaign strategy (as compared to another). Here we are dealing
with little knowledge and hard data; we are often left with guesswork, hopes
and under-informed estimations. This ignorance should result in greater
humility and less dogmatism on this topic, and a call for formal training in areas that might bring in some useful
information to help us answer these questions about means, such as economics,
marketing, consumer psychology, statistics and so forth. We should agree that
we don’t know what we need to know to bring about our desired end, and turn our
focus towards gaining that knowledge.
A second
reason why these debates shouldn’t be divisive is that it is not clear that
they are philosophical ones. As suggested above, they are largely empirical and
scientific. Our ends do not obviously dictate our means. Suppose we lived a few
hundred years ago, came to believe that slavery was wrong and should be
abolished, not merely made more “humane.” We have set our ends, but what means
should we use to achieve that end ASAP? Back then, there was no obvious answer,
for reasons comparable to those mentioned about. These issues were debated then
(and are still debated now, since human slavery still exists) and animal
advocates can surely learn from studying that debate.
Animal Advocates Promoting
Animal Use?
As a concrete example of the issue above, some animal
advocacy organizations have recently begun giving a “platform” for animal-use
industries, especially those who practice so-called “humane” farming. Whether
this is an effective (or dismal) strategic means to help bring about an “animal
rights” end, or whether this should be seen as a statement that the morally
acceptable end really is “welfarism” is something that many activists have
begun debating.
Illegal Actions
Let us now turn to some more controversial forms of
activism. Consider “open rescues” of animals from farms: these typically
involve trespass, breaking and entering, and theft of animals that are somebody’s property. All these actions are illegal. Some people argue that such rescues are morally wrong because they
are illegal. They might argue similarly against any form of activism that
involves illegal activity.
These are unsound arguments and
nearly everyone agrees with that because nearly everyone believes that this
unstated premise, which is essential to the argument, is false:
Necessarily, if an action is
illegal, then it is morally impermissible.
Hiding Jews from Nazi’s was illegal, yet morally
permissible; helping slaves escape to freedom was illegal, yet morally
permissible. Many more examples make the same point. Contrary to a common
reaction, these examples do not make any “comparisons” whatsoever between animal issues and slavery or human holocausts[2];
they are simply used to show that any (or just about any) argument against some
kind of activism based on the premise that it is illegal is unsound (or, at
least, just about everyone’s beliefs entail that it is unsound, since they
think the above premise is false: just because something is illegal does not
necessarily entail that it is morally wrong).
Animal advocates are advised to
read Martin Luther King, Jr.’s 1963 “Letter from a Birmingham Jail.”[3]
They will find much to resonate with Dr. King’s discussion.
Violent Actions
More controversial forms of activism involve violence or
threats of violence of different kinds. Violence comes in many different forms,
as our authors observe.
Some animal advocates, e.g., some
members of the ALF (Animal Liberation Front), engage in property destruction
(e.g., of animal cages, computers with experimental data, etc.) and even
sometimes even arson. Although they claim that their actions are “non-violent,”
this strains the concept of violence. They argue that since they are not
violent to anyone, i.e., they do not
inflict bodily harm on anyone, they thereby act non-violently.
This inference does not follow: one
can act violently yet do no violence to anyone. For example, it seems to make
perfect sense to say that someone could violently
smash carton of fruits and vegetables with a sledgehammer, especially if the
person was in a heated frenzy. One might not want young children to see such a
spectacle because, well, it’s too violent! So the ALF’s insistence that they
are always non-violent strains the meaning of the term.
Perhaps they (and animal use industries)
want to insist that they are non-violent because they think this principle is
true:
All acts of violence are morally
impermissible.
If this were true, and they acted violently (in performing
arson, or in how they treat animals, for example), that would imply that they
were acting wrongly.
But the above principle is false,
according to most people: violence can be, and often is, morally justified. If
violence (or threats of violence) are needed for self-defense, then it’s
permissible. If it’s needed to defend an innocent third party, then it’s
justified. Perhaps some wars can be justified. So the above principle is false,
according to most people.
Most people might even think that
it’s false regarding some animals too: if someone tried to attack your dog or
cat, might you be morally justified in responding with violence, or threats of
violence, to defend your companion animal, if needed? What if the animal was a
stray? What if the animal was in a farm, slaughterhouse or lab? If they knew
the details of the case, perhaps many people might think that violence, if
needed for defending animals, would be morally permissible in at least some of
these cases.
So perhaps violence could be justified in cases of rescue. Whether
violence can ever be justified for any other purposes, e.g., in an attempt to
change society’s general views about our obligations to animals, seems
extremely doubtful. In fact, given all the relevant considerations, it is
likely that any such violence, including possible genuine “terrorism,” would be deeply morally wrong, for reasons
that Regan, Singer and Rowlands articulate.
Discussion Questions
[1] Some might observe that, in practice,
those who call themselves “welfarists” or “advocates of animal welfare”
typically accept just about any use of animals, i.e., they deem just about all
harmful uses of animals as “necessary” and/or respecting “animal welfare.” This
may be true, but it doesn’t show that welfarism is false. This may, however,
suggest that there really is no clearly defined view “welfarism”: it’s just
some words that people use but the view really has no implications for animal
use because we can’t pin it down in any rigorous way. See Gary Francione’s
writings for discussion (Google).
[2] For an insightful discussion of such
comparisons, see Karen Davis’s The
Holocaust and the Henmaid’s Tale: A Case for Comparing Atrocities (Lantern,
2005). http://www.upc-online.org/
[3] Widely reposted online; http://www.stanford.edu/group/King/frequentdocs/birmingham.pdf
No comments:
Post a Comment