For the best formatting of this chapter's text, please download the free PDF file and/or purchase the paperback.
Overview:
This Chapter we will survey the most influential general
moral theories that have been appealed to argue in defense of animal use and/or
to object to the theories developed in defense of animals. As we will see,
these theories are often extensions or developments of the moral theories that
have been developed to explain how humans ought to treat other human beings.
These writers often argue that the moral theory (or theories) that best explain the nature and extent of
our moral obligations to human beings (especially vulnerable ones, such as
babies, children, the mentally challenged, the elderly, and so on) do not have positive implications for
animals. Thus, they argue that there are relevant
differences between the kinds of cases that justify protecting all human
beings but allowing serious harms to animals.
General Theories and Particular Cases
Like last Chapter, we want to try to focus on these theories in themselves and their implications
for animals “in general,” without so much focus on what they imply for
particular uses of animals, e.g., for food, fashion experimentation,
entertainment, and other purposes. This
will likely be harder than last Chapter because many objections to pro-animal
theories come from particular cases, e.g. arguments like these:
1.
Animal experimentation is morally permissible,
if not obligatory.
2.
But if Regan’s theory is true, then animal
experimentation is wrong.
3.
Therefore, Regan’s theory of animal rights is
mistaken.
1.
There’s nothing wrong with raising animals to
eat them.
2.
But if there’s nothing wrong with raising
animals to eat them, then animals’ interests don’t deserve equal consideration.
3.
If animals’ interests don’t deserve equal
consideration, then Singer’s theory is false.
4.
Therefore, Singer’s theory is false.
Of course, we want to know for what reasons we should accept these first premises, especially if we are
familiar with ethics!
But perhaps a way to avoid some of
these particular cases about animals at this time is to focus on what the
theories of the critics of pro-animal thinking imply for human beings,
especially the young, old, weak and powerless. Various kinds of
contractarianisms support poor treatment of animals, but they seem to support
poor treatment of humans as well, and so contractarians often feel a need to
defend themselves from these objections. Maybe these theories can sometimes be
better evaluated from the more neutral concern of human-to-human ethics.
In evaluating moral theories and
thinking about ethics in general, you want to try to have your principles or
theories have the right implications for particular cases and have those
implications for the right reasons. Unfortunately, there is no exact formula
for doing this! Ethics can be hard.
Necessary Conditions for Taking Someone’s Interests Seriously:
Cases Against Animals
While animal advocates focus on sufficient conditions for someone being in “The Moral Club” (as Rowlands
puts it), anti-animal theorists tend to focus on necessary conditions, claiming that:
We must take a being’s interests
seriously, it’s wrong to harm it (except for very good reasons), we must
respect it, etc., only if it is like this: ___.
They then typically fill in that blank with rather
cognitively advanced abilities: sophisticated reasoning, thinking about one’s
thinking, intellectual achievement, religious worship, and so on.
Their challenge, of course, comes
from the fact that many human beings lack such sophisticated minds, yet we
think we must take their interests seriously. This problem for anti-animal
theorists is known as the “argument from marginal cases.” To get around it,
these theorists often attempt to do some intellectual acrobatics, trying to
relate non-mentally sophisticated human beings (who seem to lack the stated
necessary condition for, e.g., having any moral rights) to sophisticated human
beings in peculiar ways. We will attempt to pin down their reasoning and see if
it seems to be generally valid or is developed as an ad hoc response to this
problem or worse.
Finding Relevant Differences from Arguments from Paradigm Cases:
Inference to Better Moral
Explanations?
Regarding above, anti-animal thinkers need to offer
explanations of the clear cut cases of wrongs to human beings and not have those explanations have
positive implications for animals.
Common Invalid Arguments
An argument is invalid when the premises do not logically
lead to the conclusion. Many objections to cases against animals are of a
common invalid argument form called “denying the antecedent,” where the
premises do not lead to the conclusion or the conclusion logically follow from
the premises. This argument is invalid:
1.
If
conscious, sentient animals have moral rights then seriously harming them is typically wrong.
2.
But animals do not have any moral
rights.
3.
Therefore, animal experimentation is
morally permissible.
This argument is of the same invalid pattern as this argument:
1.
If you (the reader) were a professional
basketball player, then you would be over a foot tall. [TRUE!]
2.
But you are not a professional basketball
player. [TRUE!?]
3.
Therefore,
you are not over a foot tall. [FALSE]
Non-professional basketball players should see that these
premises are true but the conclusion false: this means that the premises do not
lead to the conclusion. The same is true about the first argument above, since
the pattern is the same. The point applies to this invalid argument too:
1.
If animals are “equal” to humans, as “important”
has humans, have the same “moral status” as humans, then seriously harming them
is typically wrong.
2.
But animals are not “equal” to humans, not as “important”
has humans, and do have the same “moral status” as humans.
3.
Therefore, seriously harming them is not typically wrong.
Furthermore, what it means
to say these things about “equality,” “importance,” and “moral status” are not at all clear: much explanation would be
needed for the kind of understanding needed to decide whether this claim is
true or false.
No comments:
Post a Comment