For the best formatting of this chapter's text, please download the free PDF file and/or purchase the paperback.
Overview:
This chapter will survey the most influential “theories of
animal ethics,” i.e., general theories that attempt to explain the nature and
extent of our moral obligations toward animals, which have been used to argue
in defense of animals. As we will see, these theories are often extensions or
developments of the moral theories that have been developed to explain how
humans ought to treat other human beings. These thinkers often argue that the
moral theory (or theories) that best
explain the nature and extent of our moral obligations to human beings
(especially vulnerable ones, such as babies, children, the mentally challenged,
the elderly, and so on) have positive implications for many animals as well.
Thus, they often argue that there are no relevant
differences between the kinds of cases to justify protecting human beings
but allowing serious harms to animals and, therefore, animals are due moral
protections comparable to at least those given to comparably-conscious, aware,
sentient human beings.
General Theories and Particular Cases
This Chapter will get an initial presentation of three of
the most influential methods of moral thinking for human to human interactions that have been extended to apply to human to animal interactions, i.e., how
humans ought to treat non-human animals.
These perspectives are, first, a
demand for equality or equal moral
consideration of interests
(developed by Peter Singer; however he sometimes describes his ethical theory
as a form of utilitarianism, although
his book Animal Liberation does not
presuppose it); second, a demand for respect of the moral right to respectful
treatment (developed by Tom Regan); and, third, a demand that moral
decisions be made fairly and impartially
and the use of a novel thought experiment designed to ensure this (developed by
Mark Rowlands, following John Rawls, the most influential political philosopher
of the twentieth century).
We want to try to focus on these theories in themselves and their implications
for animals “in general,” without so much focus on what they imply for
particular uses of animals, e.g., for food, fashion experimentation,
entertainment, and other purposes. This
attempt to make things a bit more abstract and general might seem forced, and
we will surely understand the theories more deeply more when we see them
applied to particular cases. Nevertheless, we want to try to evaluate these
theories as true or false, well-supported or not, on their own terms.
Arguments from Paradigm Cases: Inference to the Best Moral
Explanation
Earlier we saw that scientists (and philosophers) sometimes
use a pattern of reasoning known as inference
to the best explanation to explain non-moral phenomena, e.g., the existence
of minds. Ethicists use this form of reasoning also, although what is usually
being explained is some clear moral intuition, or a moral judgment that nearly
everyone agrees on (and seemingly for good reason). Again, the pattern is
something like this:
- A moral judgment – J – seems true, and what makes it true requires explanation.
- Moral explanation or hypothesis T best explains the truth of J (i.e.,
T is a better explanation than other candidate explanations in that it
makes sense of more of the data/observations/similar moral intuitions,
allows us to make other moral judgments (thus enabling a kind of
prediction, perhaps), is simpler, fits with pre-existing knowledge, etc.)
- Therefore,
probably T, and what’s entailed
by T, are true.
Singer seems to use this pattern of reasoning, starting with
the widely accepted moral judgments that racism
and sexism (and other prejudices) are wrong. He gives an analysis of what
racism and sexism are – they are not
easy to define – and gives an explanation for why they are wrong, arguing that this explanation is a better
explanation than some rival explanations. He then argues that this explanation,
which appeals to the principle of
equality of consideration of interests, has positive implications for
animals. Since many animals have
interests, the prejudice that results in their interests being ignored is speciesism.
Regan argues similarly, starting
with the informed intuition that the men in the Tuskegee Syphilis Study were
treated wrongly (p. 44; elsewhere he uses historical cases of harmful medical
experiments on retarded children[1]).
He argues that the best explanation
why they way these men (and children) were treated was wrong has positive
implications for animals. He argues that these men had moral rights to life,
bodily integrity, and respectful treatment. He develops the “subject of a life”
sufficient condition for having basic moral rights to life, to bodily integrity
and respectful treatment, shows that this criterion for moral rights applies to
many animals as well, and that they thereby have moral rights as well.
In both cases, the pattern is to
start with what we are confident with, think about the best reasons to support
that confident judgment, and see that that these reasons have implications for
areas that we perhaps have not thought about as carefully. We then see that
that we have to revise our previous judgments about that new kind of case or, if we are to be consistent, revise our
initial judgments (e.g., about the human cases), or argue that nothing follows
from one kind of case to another because they are relevantly dissimilar.
Singer, Regan and Rowlands, as well as the others, are clear on the logical
options.
Sufficient Conditions for Taking Someone’s Interests Seriously
The cases for animals can be seen as an attempt to identify
this ‘this’ here:
If a being is like this ____, then we must take its
interests seriously, it’s wrong to harm it (except for very good reasons), we
must respect it, etc.
Animal advocates typically argue that if we look at what we
think about human beings, it appears that we think (or should think) that all human beings, especially those who
are vulnerable – the very young and old – deserve such protections: e.g., none
should be eaten, worn and experimented on. These philosophers argue that, for
human beings, we seem to think the ‘this’ above is just consciousness or
sentience or, as Regan puts it, being a “subject of a life,” and that this is a
sufficient condition for it being the
case that a being is wrong to harm. They argue that this principle applies to
(some) animals as well, those animals that possess the relevant characteristics
that humans have.
Most critics of this reasoning
attempt to find other characteristics that would account for the wrongness of
harming human beings, but seek characteristics that only human beings have and
no animals have. The challenge is, first, finding these characteristics and,
second, explaining why they are morally relevant.
"We will examine two rights theories – Regan’s and Rowlands’ – in detail. While these theories typically support the view that most harmful uses of animals are morally permissible,..." You may have meant to say "not permissible".
ReplyDeleteYes, another error. Boo!
Delete