For the best formatting of this chapter's text, please download the free PDF file and/or purchase the paperback.
Overview
If any animals have minds, and thus are conscious, then they
can be harmed, and thus how they are treated raises moral issues. And,
arguably, there are moral obligations towards animals only if they have minds, so questions about animal ethics very much
depend on what animals are like. This Chapter we will get an overview of the
scientific and philosophical literature on whether any animals are conscious,
whether any are sentient (i.e., capable of sensation or feeling, especially of
pleasures and pains), and so whether various species of animals have minds and,
if so, what their mental, psychological and/or emotional lives might be like.
We will discuss how anyone could know or reasonably believe some claim about
animals’ minds.
Being Specific About Species
In the first lecture on logic, I made these two suggestions
about identifying arguments:
These suggestions are relevant to thinking about animals’
minds since the category of “animal” is extremely broad: “animals” range from
unicellular organisms, insects, invertebrates, vertebrates, birds, and to
mammals of different kinds, including primates (like human beings). Since there
are millions of species of animals, so when investigate whether animals’ have
minds, the natural questions are, “Which
animals?” or, “What do you mean by
‘animals’? Which animals are you referring to?”
Sometimes we forget to notice that
these same questions should often be asked about human beings’ mental lives.
The mental lives of, e.g., newborn babies, five year olds, “normal” adults,
cognitively disabled individuals, and Alzheimer’s patients surely differ
greatly. So if someone says that (all) animals don’t have minds like human
beings’ minds, we should ask which
human beings, since many some, if not, many animals have mental lives
comparable to, if not richer than, many human beings’ minds. That’s a
possibility: whether we should think it’s true, of course, depends on what the
research shows about the varieties of animals’ and humans’ minds and mental
capacities.
Our readings primarily focus on
mammals and birds, although there is some discussion of fish, invertebrates
(such as octopi) and even some research on insects. But, again, it seems likely
the minds of different mammals (if any have minds) are also different: e.g., a
mouse’s mental life is likely quite different from a chimpanzee’s (especially
if that chimp has been taught sign language). Additional research on different
kinds of animals’ minds will be discussed in later sections of the course:
e.g., research on the minds of chickens, cows and pigs will be discussed in the
sections on animal agriculture; rats and mice, cats, dogs and primates in the
sections of animal experimentation, and so on.
How Do We Know? Arguments from Analogy & Inference to the
Best Scientific Explanation
Epistemology is an
area of philosophy that asks how we know
things and what it is for a belief to be reasonable
and supported by good evidence. How
might we know that any animals have
minds, or reasonably believe any such claims? We can call this question “The
Epistemological Problem of Animal Minds.”
Before we think about this (hard)
problem, it’s worthwhile to mention that philosophers (and some psychologists
and neuroscientists) worry about a more general (hard) problem called “The
Epistemological Problem of Other Minds” regarding humans’ minds. The problem is that each of us only has “direct
access” to our own perceptions, thoughts and feelings: we cannot directly “see”
that anyone else is conscious and has a mind. All we see is external, overt
behavior (including speech) and, presumably, somehow infer from this behavior that another individual has thoughts,
feelings and perceptions somewhat like our own. Perhaps this inference is not
consciously made, but how else could we know that other people have minds?!
Believe it or not, this question
has troubled philosophers for millennia and there is no widely accepted answer.
Many philosophers argue, however, that we know that other people have minds
either by reasoning by analogy or by reasoning from the best explanation of some
phenomena, in this case the overt behavior.
To reason by analogy is, most
simply, to reason like this:
·
Thing 1 has these characteristics a, b,
and c;
·
Thing 2 has characteristics a & b;
·
Thing 2 is relevantly
similar to Thing 1;
·
Therefore,
probably Thing 2 has characteristic c too.
Or, even more simply: “These two things are similar in the
relevant ways, so therefore what is true of one is probably true of the other.”
The strength of an argument from analogy depends on how similar to two things
are: the more similar, the stronger the analogy, obviously, and more likely the
conclusion is to be true.
To respond to the “Problem of other
Minds,” someone might reason, “I behave these ways, have this kind of biology,
and I have a mind. Other people
behave in similar ways and have similar biology. Therefore, they probably have minds too.” It’s important to observe
that we apparently often use the same kind of kind of reasoning about animals’
minds, as our authors demonstrate.
The second common pattern of
reasoning about minds is an argument from the best explanation:
·
There is some event that requires explanation.
·
Explanation or hypothesis E best explains that event (i.e., is a better explanation than other
candidate explanations in that it makes sense of more of the data/observations,
allows predication, is simpler, fits with pre-existing knowledge, etc.)
·
Therefore,
probably E, and what’s entailed by E,
are true.
This pattern of reasoning is often applied to animal
behavior: an animal does something (e.g., reacts in some interesting way to new
surroundings); we try to figure out if this reaction would be better explained
on the hypothesis that (a) this animal is a mindless automaton or (b) this
animal has a conscious mind (or some other explanation, perhaps with greater
details than [b]). How this reasoning will work out very much depends on the details of the case, but it’s important to
note that we use this pattern of reasoning to investigate both humans’ and
animals’ minds.
A Source of Doubts: Necessary Conditions for Having a Mind
Many who argue (or have argued, in the case of historical
figures) that animals don’t have minds often claim that there is (or are) necessary condition(s) for having a
mind, animals lack that necessary condition, and therefore they are mindless.
So, some have claimed that a being has a mind only if, e.g., that being has language, and argued that animals are
mindless since they can’t speak. Critics tend to challenge these claims by
either arguing that that (some) animals meet this necessary condition, or by
arguing that it’s false that this condition is a necessary one: a being can
have a mind even if it lacks this condition. They also tend to point out that
that many such principles imply that human infants are mindless, which seems to
be false (and perhaps must be false, since such infants do learn language, and
that can happen only if they have minds already, before having language).
These are a few central concepts to keep in mind while
reading the interesting and informative readings for this lecture.
I believe you missed a critical element in this topic which is intelligence. Only humans are known to argue to the point of fighting for the interests of others even if they do not share such views or interests. Case in point is affirmative action in the US. I am agreeable that animals are conscious of their physical and environmental stages. However that does not directly translate into intelligence in human terms. Until break through is achieved in intellectual communication between the species, there is no way of ascertaining that animals are deserving the same consideration as the humans. Even as we speak humans are still struggling to establish equality among people of color and white race. You have not convinced me to allocate the same rights to animals by the above. Culturally speaking, island societies are more mindful of their meager resources. We kill only what we can eat. On a last note, we talk to our trees before cutting them down for our use. Would that make them deserving of rights too?
ReplyDeleteThanks for your comment. There is some research on empathy and altruism in (some) animals, which might be similar to the kind of "intelligence" you describe.
Delete"Critics tend to challenge these claims by either arguing that that (some) animals..." might be a typo.
ReplyDeleteIt would definitely be a typo!
DeleteI should reprocess this text using the program "Grammarly" which didn't exist when I wrote this!